Imágenes de páginas
PDF
EPUB
[ocr errors]

insurance against risk; and, if ill success continues. a loss of capital will result. The converse would apply where the history of a company was more favourable than had been expected at the time when the investment was made; and there might well be an appreciation of capital altogether independent of the provision available in insurance against risk.

will replace the value of the machines by the time they are worn out. But machines suffer not only from wear and tear, but from the risk of being superseded. In so far as this contingency differs from that due to variations in trade, a further provision will be required, and depreciation and a contribution towards obsolescence together constitute a species of insurance resembling life insurance as applied to inanimate things. In fact, this analogy has been so fully recognized that it is usual to speak of the life of a mine,' and the process just described is often termed 'amortization' -i.e. the formation of a fund which will make good the capital outlay when the source of income will have expired. In like manner, any use of capital in a business which is subject to risk may be described as having only a limited life. The principle of the spreading of risks has been applied here, partly through the agency of the joint-stock system, whereby the investor, instead of risking his resources in one enterprise which may result in a total loss of his capital, distributes his funds in several investments, and, if he displays equal judgment in each case, both his income and his capital are likely to fluctuate less on a system of dividing the risk. The same result is attained by Investment Trust companies, where the stock-insured, but to the community. Besides, there are holder who makes only a single investment has the advantage of participating in the united results of many employments of capital. In addition he should gain by the specialized knowledge of the officials, though the practice of forming investment trusts in order to place capital in a certain country or a certain industry may lessen the full gain from a system of averaging. It is obvious that, in these instances, the method adopted is an application of the principles of insurance.

[ocr errors]

If one asks, Why should people risk their capital in enterprises of a hazardous nature?' the answer is not quite so easy as it might appear at first sight. A little consideration will show that the gains in appreciation of investments must at least balance the losses in depreciation, after allowance is made for the interest which would have been received on a first class security. But, as is well known, uses of capital, which are subject to business risks, commonly return a higher rate of income per cent than those that are more secure. Accordingly, the difference between the rate of interest on a perfectly secure investment (known as 'interest proper' or 'economic interest') and that returned by capital employed subject to hazard constitutes a fund as against depreciation of the capital. This difference is known as 'insurance against risk.' Such insurance, it should be noted, is only a partial one. It may be supposed to suffice to make good wastage of capital (after allowance is made for increments to capital value of other investments) on the whole and over long periods. Thus it is insurance against depreciation of trading capital over the whole community. But this is not insurance for the individual. If what may be termed the expectation of life of his investment at the time he makes it is exactly borne out by events, even though at the end of that time his original capital will have disappeared, he will have received not only economic interest but, in excess of that, a sufficient amount to replace at least the amount of his first investment. Such a phenomenon is rare : the prospects of undertakings subject to business risks change from day to day. Even though, after the investment is made, these become less favourable, he has no opportunity of increasing his insurance against risk, since its rate is determined, once for all, by the price paid for the stock, the dividend then paid, and the rate of economic interest at that time. The decline in prosperity will contract the estimated sum available for

VOL. VII.-24

Insurance, both in its common forms and in its wider signification, has important advantages, both for the individual and for the community. It lessens the dislocation of industry which would otherwise arise through the cessation of production by some firm that has sustained a sudden calamity through a fire which destroyed all its works, or any other similar disaster. In fact, in so far as insurance tends to make production more uniform, it tends to augment its efficiency. Similarly it makes labour more efficient also, since it relieves all those workers who have persons depending on their earnings from the harrowing anxiety as to the pecuniary position of those persons in the event of the early death of the earner of the income. Further, the system undoubtedly prevents cases of actual poverty which would otherwise have arisen. It is thus beneficial not only to the families of persons important psychological effects. The necessity of the punctual payment of premiums tends to form habits of saving, which are valuable towards the accumulation of capital in a country. For these reasons Governments are disposed to encourage life insurance as well as certain other forms of insurance. The encouragement takes various forms, such as the provision of statistical material and departmental supervision. In Great Britain income tax is rebated on that part of an income, otherwise subject to it, which is employed in the payment of life insurance premiums. These aids are of the nature of indirect bounties on insurance, and on the Continent cases occur where direct bounties are paid by the State. In the National Insurance Act, the principle of a double direct bounty to the insured (i.e. in the contributions of the State and the employer) is adopted, reinforced by compulsion. The latter element conflicts with some of the accessory advantages of insurance, e.g. in the formation of habits of thrift. At the same time, even in the case of ordinary life insurance, while the person who insures himself is free in law to discontinue the payment of his premiums and to obtain the surrender value (if any) of his policy, once a policy has been begun, in the great majority of cases there is a feeling almost amounting to compulsion towards the maintaining of the insurance. The problem in relation to the insurance of the working classes is in reality a choice of the line of least disadvantage. Bounties would maintain the voluntary principle, and would extend its appli cations under a certain artificial stimulus. Compulsion secures at once that, in a properly devised scheme, a greater number of persons obtain the benefits. Every effort has been made to conserve as much individual action as is possible, within a scheme of general compulsion, by associating Friendly Societies with the actual working of the Act.

[ocr errors]

Finally, the tendency to the more exact gradation and valuation of general business risks has important social effects. Here, too, there is a development in averaging, and thus the hazard of uncertainty tends, on the whole, to be reduced. The element of uncertainty-bearing' in production thus becomes more efficient. Hence, on the whole, the provision required for insurance against risk can be reduced with safety; and, therefore, pro tanto there is an economy in production. Further, external circumstances co-operate in increasing the

|

As Beare sayı

saving. Outside the risks insured by underwriters, New York, 1888, p. 256, note).
there remain many uncertainties, which are gradu-
ally being reduced by improvements in organiza-
tion, by increase in commercial knowledge and
experience, and by developments in communication.
The last two always afford increased opportunities
of averaging, while the first lessens the amount of
uncertainty, and in favourable circumstances may
remove large classes of transactions from this
category altogether.

(Greek Theories of Elementary Cognition, p. 273),
'It may help us to understand Plato's distribution better if,
distinguishing alonois as we have done into two elements, the
element of feeling and the element of cognition, we refer the
which has its seat in the cranium.'

LITERATURE.-A. A. Cournot, Exposition de la théorie des chances et des probabilités, Paris, 1843; F. Y. Edgeworth, Metritike, or the Method of measuring Probability and Utility, London, 1887; J. Venn, The Logic of Chance, do. 1888; H. Westergaard, Grundzüge der Theorie der Statistik, Jena, 1890; J. Kozák, Grundlehren der Wahrscheinlichkeitsrechnung, als Vorstufe für das Studium der Fehlerausgleichung, Schiesstheorie, und Statistik, Vienna, 1912; H. Poincaré, Calcul des probabilités, Paris, 1912; L. Bachelier, Calcul des probabilités, do. 1912; A. L. Bowley, Elements of Statistics, London, 1907; H. C. Emery, The Place of the Speculator in the Theory of Distribution (Publications of American Economic Association, 3rd ser., vol. ì. no. 1); A. H. Willett, Economic Theory of Risk and Insurance, New York, 1901; J. Haynes, Risk as an economic Factor, Quarterly Journal of Economics, ix. (Boston, 1888); A. C. Pigou, Wealth and Welfare, London, 1912. In addition to the above works, reference may be made to the standard works on the theory of Political Economy, in which references to insurance against risk will be found-e.g., the treatises of Bullock, Chapman, Ely, Fetter, Flux, Gide, Hadley, Marshall, Nicholson, Seager, Seligman, Taussig, Walker, and W. R. SCOTT.

Wicksteed.

INTELLECT.-A. Bain says: Thought, Intellect, Intelligence, or Cognition includes the powers known as Perception, Memory, Conception, Abstraction, Reason, Judgment, and Imagination. It is analyzed, as will be seen, into three functions, called Discrimination or Consciousness of Difference, Similarity or Consciousness of Agreement, and Retentiveness or Memory' (Mental and Moral Science, London, 1884, p. 2).

Sully (Human Mind, i. 64) objects to the inclusion of retentiveness among the functions of intellect, on the grounds that it is not confined to the phenomena of intellect, but underlies the processes of feeling and willing as well; that the representation, like the sense-impression, is nothing but material for the process of intellection; and that the revival of past impressions takes place according to laws of association which are closely connected with the processes of assimilation and integration. Sully substitutes for retentiveness, as the third function of intellect, associative integration or the connecting of a given material with its concomitants in time and place.

If we exclude the presentations of sense and the representations of memory and imagination, 'intellect' is the name given to the higher cognitive powers of the mind. It may be considered as identical with what Sir W. Hamilton called Thought Proper, the Faculty of Comparison, and also to include what he called the Regulative Faculty-the Faculty of Principles. So understood, it includes the voûs and diávoia of the Greeks, and stands opposed to merely sensitive knowledge, although always regarded as standing in close inter-connexion with the latter.

While the above may be taken as roughly describing what intellect means in almost any system of philosophy or psychology, yet the whole significance of the description depends on the way in which intellect is conceived to stand to sensation, feeling, will, and the psychic principle itself.

In the Platonic philosophy, the soul is, so to speak, externally related to the body. It exists in the body as a detached principle, which directs and controls it, as the charioteer the chariot. Although Plato distinguishes various parts of the soul, or even various kinds of soul, still it is only through the soul considered as intellect, as pure thought, that the passions of the irrational part are known (R. D. Archer-Hind, Phado, London, 1883, Introd. p. 30). The same holds true of sensu ous perception (Archer-Hind, Timæus, London and

latter element of aigenous uniformly to the intellectual soul,

Sensation, therefore, as known, is an affection of the pure psychic principle, and is not to be regarded as something sui generis, distinct from intellect. It is rather to be regarded as a phase of intellectual activity itself-intellect entering into relation with phenomena.

In the philosophy of Aristotle, the psychic prin ciple occupies a different position. It is not related to the body as agent to instrument, but as form to matter, as relatum to correlate, as entelechy, actualization of what the body potentially is. It is not, in itself, purely intellectual. Not only do the merely vital activities proceed from the same principle which exerts the cognitive activities, but the latter also, at least those which belong to sense and imagination, stand in the same conditioning and conditioned relation to the organism in which the vital activities stand. If Aristotle had remained at this standpoint, he would have held a position substantially identical with modern Sensationism, as we find it, for example, in Bain, which reduces intellect to a mere self-elaboration of the fundamental attributes of sensation-assi milation, discrimination, retention-a system in which relations of similarity and difference between sensations are conceived to become the conscious apprehension of resemblance and difference as such.

Aristotle, however, did not remain at this position. He postulated the presence of a Divine element in the human soul-the vous, emanating from the Divine vous, and constituting the really im mortal part of man. It enters from without. Aristotle's doctrine of voûs has been a problem from his day until now. What is its relation to sensitive knowledge? The answer to this question is con tained in the celebrated doctrine of the active and passive vous — intellectus agens and intellectus patiens. The active intellect is that which illuminates the sensitive phantasm and transmutes what is there apprehended into the intelligible form which is then received by the passive intellect. But this process may be conceived in different ways. Of what nature is the transmuting process? On the one hand, the active intellect may be thought to create the form, as light does colours-in other words, to generate it on the occasion of the sensuous phantasm, so that the passive intellect does not really receive anything from the phantasmata or sensible species, but rather an entirely new creation produced from itself by the active intellect. In the Middle Ages it was maintained that no material agency could act on this immaterial intellect, nor could the latter fabricate intellectual species from the material phantasm (cf. Maher, Psychology, p. 308; and Hamilton, Reid's Works, p. 953 f., and the references there given). The species intelligibilis impressa is thus elaborated by the active intellect, and received by the passive intellect, where, together with the act of intellection, it constitutes the species intelligibilis expressa. It is consonant with this view that the active intellect and the passive intellect should be regarded as two powers or faculties, as was held by the majority of the scholastic philosophers. On the other hand, the active intellect may be regarded as playing a far less important rôle, as not producing the intelligible species, but as simply supplying the illumination, as it were, through which the passive intellect receives the intelligible form abstracted from the sensuous phantasm. From this point of view the passive

intellect is not a distinct principle, but simply the recipient phase of the active intellect.

In which form was the doctrine of the active and passive intellects held by Aristotle himself? Intellect, he says, is a distinct kind of soul' alone capable of separation as the eternal from the perishable (de Anima, 413, 26). In de Anima, 430, 10-25, he says:

'But, since in all Nature there is something which is the matter to each kind of thing and is all those things potentially; and another something which is the cause and efficient in making them all, as art is related to its material, it is necessary that in the soul also these differences should subsist. The intellect is

one thing because it becomes all things, another thing considered as it makes all things as an effective force like light; for in a manner light makes what are only potentially colours to be colours actually. And this intellect is separable and im

passive and unmixed, being in its essence activity; for the efficient is ever held more in honour than the patient, and the principle than the matter. Knowledge in activity is identical with the thing; potentially it is prior in time in the individual, but universally it is not prior in time. This intellect does not at one time think, at another not think. When separated, it is alone what it is, and this alone is immortal and eternal. But we do not remember because this intellect is not passive. The passive intellect is, however, perishable, and thinks nothing

without this.'

Aquinas and Duns Scotus regarded not only the active but also the passive intellect as distinct from the faculty of sensuous cognition.

The following modern interpretations of the passive intellect are cited by Hicks (de Anima, Introd. lxvii). F. A. Trendelenburg identifies it with all the lower faculties in contradistinction to the active intellect, E. Zeller with the sum of those faculties of representation which go beyond imagination and sensible perception and yet fall short of that higher Thought, which has found peace in perfect unity with its object, F. Ravaisson with the universal potentiality in the world of ideas, F. Brentano with 'imagination,' G. Hertling with this cognitive faculty of the sensitive part,' and W. A. Hammond with the life of sensation as a potentially rational mass,' the sum of the deliverances of sense-perceptions and their re-wrought form in memory and phantasy, regarded as potentiality.' These various interpretations, with the exception of those of Zeller and Ravaisson, really identify the passive intellect with sensitive perception, imagination, or with the sensus communis; that is, with something which is not intellect at all. This view has been ably controverted by Hicks:

If these modern interpreters were right in equating the Intellect which becomes with one or other of the lower faculties or with the sum of them, then the function of these faculties would be identical with the function of thought, so far as the intellect becomes all things. But the lower faculties, sense and imagination, never succeed in obtaining an object which is a true universal' (op. cit. lxviii).

If both the active and passive intellects are distinct from the inferior faculties of sense and imagination, are they to be regarded as two faculties, or one and the same faculty? The question has been debated both in medieval and in modern times. The answer given by Wallace, Hicks, and many schoolmen seems to be the true one. They are not two intellects, but only two different modes of viewing the same intellect. This interpretation, as pointed out above, is naturally allied to that view of the active intellect which assigns to it a very unimportant role-that merely of illuminating the image. As Hicks says, 'the functions of the latter [the active intellect] are then reduced within the narrowest compass.' Moreover, it is the passive intellect which cognizes, and which, therefore, seems to be identical with the conscious side. It was precisely one of the difficulties urged against the separation of the active and passive intellects that it seemed to make of the former a faculty blindly and instinctively operating. The intellectus agens, if distinct and viewed as creating the intelligible species, has no perception beforehand of what it creates. This difficulty is not confined to ancient philosophy. It is precisely for this reason that E. von Hartmann (Religion des Geistes, Berlin, 1882, p. 145) refuses to regard the creative idea as conscious. In relation to God, von Hartmann identifies consciousness not with a productive ideal archetype of the world, but with a

receptive ideal ectype. The parallelism of the distinction of the active and passive reason to the pure Ego and the empirical self of Fichte, and the consequent absence of consciousness in God both in Fichte's system and in Hegel's, as interpreted by the Hegelian Left, have been pointed out by Pringle- Pattison (Hegelianism and Personality, London, 1887, pp. 46, 226). The present writer has maintained (Objectivity of Truth, London, 1884, p. 106 f.) that, alike in the human and the Divine thinking, the two aspects coincide and are to be conceived as one. Intellect in its very receptiveness is determinative, and receptive in its determinativeness. If this determinativeness is regarded as a continuously acting timeless activity, we have, perhaps, the true conception of the Aristotelian active intellect, resembling the intuitus originarius of Kant. An opposite view is taken by A. E. Biedermann (Christliche Dogmatik2, Berlin, 1884-85, §§ 698-717), who emphasizes the diametrical opposition in the relation of the Absolute and of the finite spirit to material existence. Cf. Spinoza, Ethics, i. prop. xvii. schol.

The mention of Kant's intuitus_originarius brings before us another great problem in the interpretation of Aristotle's doctrine of the intellect which we have deferred till now. Is the intellect Divine or human? There are three views possible. (1) The active intellect, vous TonTIKÓS, may be identified with the Deity and regarded as communicating itself to individual men, the passive intellect, intellectus possibilis, voûs wαontiKós, belonging merely to the individual soul. This view was held by Alexander the Aphrodisian, and by Avicenna, who, however, substitutes for the Deity a lower intelligence that has proceeded by a series of emanations from Him (Stöckl, Gesch. der Philos. des Mittelalters, ii. 1. 42). (2) Averroes separates both the active and possible or material intellect from the individual soul, and regards it as it, however, not with the Deity Himself, but, like one and the same intellect in all men, identifying Avicenna, with an emanation from the Deity (ib. 113).1 (3) Aquinas and the medieval scholastics regard the intellect, active and passive, as a faculty of the individual human soul. The first of these interpretations is exposed to the difficulty that it separates the active and passive intellects so that they cannot act together (cf. Aquinas, contra Gent. II. clxxvi.). The second interpretation makes both the active intellect and the apprehension of the rational concept the act not of the human intellect, but of an intellect outside the individual human being, and one and the same in all men. Such a conception divorces intellect so completely from the individual soul that it is hard to conceive how any tie remains between them. The third interpretation is exposed to great difficulties. Unless conceived as a distinct faculty apart from the passive intellect, it becomes little more than a phase of the latter. It can only be regarded as illuminative of the Divine creative thought, already implicitly present in the phantasm. If the active intellect is conceived as something distinct from the passive-and Aquinas did so regard it-it is difficult to understand how a merely human faculty, acting instinctively or blindly, can be creative of an intelligible species which, nevertheless, has an ideal community or identity with the independently existing phantasm. Lastly, it seems impossible to understand how a human intellectus agens should be in perpetual activity, still more a speculative intellect that

1 In medieval philosophy the intellectus possibilis is, in general, identical with the passive intellect. They were distinguished by some of the Arabians, but, as in that case the passive intellect is identified with some of the interpretations already rejected, a bare mention of that fact is sufficient here.

combines both active and passive intellect (see Hicks' de Anima, note 430, a. 22).

A solution of these difficulties in Aristotle's doctrine may possibly be found if we view him as regarding vous in its relation to the human soul as a Divine-human faculty or power-on the human side active and passive at once, on the Divine ever active, for the activity of intellect is life. This agrees with the language of the Nic. Ethics (x. 7), that vous is 'something Divine' -'the true self.'

[blocks in formation]

conception of intellect which we find in the Association school. This school makes feeling, sensation, the fundamental phenomenon of psy. chical and of rational life. Intellect, intelligence, is only the development of the most fundamental features of sensation. Similarity, discrimination, retention, beget by means of the continued action of association the cognitive apprehension of objects distinct, or apparently distinct, from sensations themselves. It is unnecessary to repeat the wellknown criticisms to which this doctrine is exposed. The unity of consciousness, through which similarity and difference are recognized, and which imparts significance to retention, is unexplained. In general, Associationists put the cart before the horse. In the most important activities of mind, phenomena are associated because they are cogcertain psychical events are associated. The same applies to the Herbartian school. As Höffding says, 'Consciousness is not merely a platform on which ideas carry on their struggle for existence; it acts itself in and through the individual ideas' (Outlines of Psychology, Eng. tr., London, 1896, p. 144).

Owing perhaps to the influence of A. Schopenhauer and F. Nietzsche, a tendency has shown itself in recent philosophy, especially in Pragmat ism, to regard intellect no longer as the refined product of Association, but as the creature and instrument of the will.

According to Schopenhauer, nature has produced the intellect for the service of an individual will: therefore it is destined only to know things so far as they furnish the motives of such a will but not to fathom them or apprehend their essence in itself' (Werke, ed. J. Frauenstädt, Leipzig, 1877, iii. 156). To Nietzsche Reason is only a tool' (Jenseits von Gut und Böse, do. 1896, p. 122).

The relation of the Aristotelian doctrine of in-nized as related, not cognized as related because tellect to the question of the immortality of the soul depends on the relation in which intellect and sense are conceived to stand to consciousness and memory. Hamilton (Reid's Works, p. 878) cites a passage from Aristotle (Probl. xi. 33) which he translates: To divorce Sensation from Understanding, is to reduce Sensation to an insensible process; wherefore it has been said-Intellect sees, and Intellect hears.' This would lead to a Platonic view, essentially identifying consciousness with the immaterial intellect. On the other hand, if the lower animals are not mere machines, their sensuous life implies some kind of consciousness. Balmes was consequently led to attribute to them an immaterial self and some sort of possible immortality (Fundamental Philosophy, bk. ii. ch. 2). That the mere animal soul is a simple immaterial substance, originating and perishing with the body, was held by S. Tongiorgi, and opposed by Stöckl, who held that matter was the substrate of the organic life of brutes (Lehrbuch der Philos.' ii. 168). Unless, therefore, intellect and sensibility can be regarded as still united in some common root, to use Kant's expression, the separability of intellect from the body seems to involve the division of consciousness itself. The doctrine of Aquinas regarding memory seems to involve a similar division of that faculty, the cognition of the past object in itself belonging to sense, and intellect preserving only the intelligible species, yet having, nevertheless, in relation to the act of intellect, though not to the object, a cognition of the past as such (Summa, I. qu. lxxix. art. 6). The real significance of Aristotle's doctrine of the intellect in its bearing on the immortality of the human soul has been disputed in every age. W. Archer Butler says:

It it not sufficient to satisfy the demands of human anxiety on this subject, that an eternity should be pronounced essential

to an active intellectual principle, which itself seems described

as unable to exercise any conscious energies apart from the bodily structure; a quickening essence whose very existence retreats into nothingness when it is left nothing to quicken (Lectures, p. 558).

The changed point of view from which intellect is regarded in modern philosophy appears in Spinoza. The intellect, whether finite or infinite, is regarded by him as only in actuality, not in potentiality; but then this intellect belongs, not to active but to passive nature, not to natura naturans but to natura naturata (Ethics, I. prop. xxxi.). Hence it does not represent a power standing over against nature, but one which is identical with nature. The same changed standpoint shows itself in Leibniz's addition to the scholastic formula, Nihil est in intellectu quod non fuerit in sensu, nisi intellectus ipse.' Intellect or reason is conceived in Leibniz and Kant as possessing a content essentially related to the objects of nature.

We have already had occasion to mention the

The possibility of conceiving the force in nature as will, impulse, does not directly concern us here, but the possibility of so conceiving the fundamental principle in mind does. When it was thought that we had in the sense of effort an immediate consciousness of energy expended, it was not unreasonable to regard the consciousness of effort not only as determinative of many of our most intellectual perceptions, but even as affording a glimpse into the metaphysical nature of reality. But, now that the existence of such a feeling is generally rejected, it is difficult to conceive the stream of consciousness merely as such as presenting a conative aspect. According to G. F. Stout, the process of consciousness is in part selfdetermining. There is in it a current, a current which it feels, a tendency towards an end (Manual of Psychology, London, 1907, p. 64 f.). Through this conative tendency the presentations of consciousness acquire objective meaning, and in general through conative continuity the processes of consciousness acquire meaning and significance. This theory seems exposed to the same objections as the Association theory. Such consciousness of an end, however vague, implies the presence of an intellectual power which already differentiates such end from the current tending towards it. Only so can the current feel itself to be tending towards

an end.

[ocr errors]

A much more decidedly voluntaristic explanation of intellect is involved in H. Münsterberg's Action Theory' (Grundzüge der Psychologie, Leipzig, 1900, i. 525). According to that theory, the liveliness of a sensation depends on the strength of the centrifugal excitation propagated from it. Sensory excitation is not in itself accompanied by psychical processes, whether the excitation proceed from the periphery or from associated centres. The afferent process is thus wholly unconscious; only in its passage into motor discharge does it give rise to consciousness. The cerebral cortex,

which is the seat of the psycho-physical processes, must, in order to produce movements, act on subcortical centres. Every sub-cortical centre stands always in connexion with an opposite centre, viz. the centre which carries out the diametrically opposite movement. This fact, according to Münsterberg, is the basis not only of all motor antagonistic functions, but also of all psychical oppositions, even such as are purely intellectual and logical. Opposition of beliefs is reducible to difference of attitude in regard to our activity in the world. Upon the spatial variations in the discharge depend the varying intellectual values of the sensations. This theory is exposed to serious physiological and psychological objections, and its application in detail has not yet been given by the author. It is necessary only to mention that, at the point of transition to motor discharge, the author seems to postulate the action of a spiritual principle which determines the path of discharge and the consequent attitude of the agent to the world. It is here that the author's relation to Fichte comes in, whose ethical idealism he claims to unite with the physiological psychology of our time. The voluntaristic theory must not be confused with the practical Reason of the Scholastics. The latter refers merely to the application of reason to the harmony of action with nature and its final end.

The voluntaristic conception of intellect appears in an interesting form in the writings of H. L. Bergson. To Bergson intellect is but a special instrument created by that élan vital which lies behind the whole process of evolution. This instrument reveals not truth, but utility. It acts not by unveiling the nature of things, but rather by limiting and falsifying the larger intuition of reality which flows through the vital impulse out of which consciousness itself issues. The falsification, however, works; it is useful for directing our activities, and is justified by its results. In fact, it is these activities which give us the forms of things. It is with inert matter, the solid, that our intelligence deals: the fluid in the real escapes it in part. Of the discontinuous and immobile alone can it form a clear idea. 'Intellect is characterized by a natural inability to comprehend life' (Bergson, Creative Evolution, Eng. tr., London, 1912, p. 174). Intellect and matter have progressively adapted themselves one to the other because it is the same inversion of the same movement which creates at once the intellectuality of mind and the materiality of things' (ib. 217). It does not appear how such a movement, even if it existed, could explain the adaptation of intellect to the object. Thought may in determining its object be determined by it (Stokes, Objectivity of Truth, p. 58 f.), but, except in the individual, this reciprocal determination does not take place as a mere process in time.

But, just as much as the psychological theories we have considered, does Bergson's biological theory of the origin of intellect imply intellect itself as already existing. He postulates a consciousness or supra-consciousness lying behind intellect. The sympathetic insight by which we penetrate the mobility of things, the supra- and ultra-intellectual intuition by which there is a taking possession of the spirit by itself-these conceptions are but intellect itself, misconstrued and misunderstood. It is the problem of the intellectus agens once again. Philosophy here treads the same ground which the followers of Aristotle have trod, and meets the same difficulties.

Grant, however, that intellect is somehow evolved out of, and is grappling more or less successfully, if not with the mystery, at any rate with the practical working of things. What does this

amount to? It means at least that the key fits the lock, and that the lock is fitted to the key. It means that nature in its working is relative, in large measure, to the concepts which intellect has framed; therefore, in still larger measure to the intelligence which has framed these concepts and will still frame others, by which nature itself will be better understood-a process which can be justified only on the presupposition, which is common alike to Aristotelian philosophy and Absolute Idealism, that nature is relative to intelligence, that vous governs all.

bridge, 1882, ed. R. D. Hicks, do. 1907; J. I. Beare, Greek LITERATURE.-Aristotle, de Anima, ed. E. Wallace, CamTheories of Elementary Cognition, Oxford, 1906; W. Hamilton, Reid's Works 7, Edinburgh, 1872, notes A and M; Aquinas, Summa, 1. qq. lxxix., lxxxv., lxxxvii., contra Gentiles, II. Ivxi.York, 1856, bks. ii., iv.; M. Maher, Psychology, New York Ixxviii.; J. L. Balmes, Fundamental Philos., Eng. tr., New and London, 1911; A. Stöckl, Lehrbuch der Philosophie Mainz, 1869 (1892); W. Archer Butler, Lectures on the Hist Lectures on Philos., do. 1885, bk. v.; A. Bain, Senses and of Anc. Philos., last series, London, 1874; T. Maguire, the Intellect, do. 1894; H. Taine, De l'Intelligence, Eng. tr., do. 1871 J. Sully, The Human Mind, do. 1892; P. Janet and G. Séailles, Hist. of the Problems of Philos., 2 vols., do. Mainz, 1864-66, and Handb. of the Hist. of Philos., pt. i., tr. 1902; A. Stöckl, Gesch. der Philos. des Mittelalters, 3 vols., T. A. Finlay, Dublin, 1887. GEORGE J. STOKES.

INTELLECTUALISM.-In its popular and most general sense, 'intellectualism' means the belief in the supremacy in human life of the intellect. More precise, technical meanings of the term appear in the theory of knowledge, in ethics, and in theology.

1. In the theory of knowledge, intellectualism is the doctrine which derives knowledge chiefly, or mainly, from the intellect, i.e. from pure reason. Intellectualism is here practically synonymous with rationalism (q.v.), and stands opposed to sensationalism (q.v.). Whereas intellectualism affirms that reason is the unique or the principal source of knowledge, and that knowledge so derived is independent of, and superior to, the impressions received from the outside world through the senses, sensationalism affirms that general ideas arise from sensations. In its extreme form, sensationalism maintains that independently of sensation the mind is a tabula rasa, that there is nothing in the mind that was not first in the sense. One may also oppose to intellectualism the systems of thought represented by Schopenhauer's philosophy, in which the will' is given a dominant role in the determination of action and the discovery of knowledge. German philosophy has been dominantly of the intellectualistic type, while sensationalism has found its most numerous exponents in France (Condorcet, d'Alembert) and in England (Locke, Hume).

The method pursued in the search for knowledge will differ according to the conception formed of its source or sources. The pure intellectualist will rely altogether upon the a priori, deductive method, the pure sensationalist upon an empirical, inductive method, since knowledge comes, according to him, through sensory experience.

2. In ethics, the intellectualistic doctrine affirms that knowledge is in itself sufficient to determine action. Socrates is the first and the chief representative of ethical intellectualism. According to him, no one does wrong knowingly. Sin is error, i.e. ignorance; for no man purposely injures himself. This doctrine is opposed by the Stoics, on the ground that the will is not altogether determined by knowledge, but is, at least in some degree, selfdetermined. Aristotle differed from Socrates in that he held it possible for desires arising from insufficient knowledge to be stronger than those proceeding from full knowledge. He thought, therefore, that the practice of virtue required not

« AnteriorContinuar »